1,166
edits
m (Zsiegel moved page Truth testing to Truth Testing) |
|||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
== Overview == | == Overview == | ||
Truth testing is a role of the ballot | Truth testing is a role of the ballot that says the judge should vote for the debater who proves the truth or falsity of the resolution. The aff burden is to prove the resolution true, and the neg burden is to prove the resolution false. | ||
Truth testing is often combined with a philosophical framework to prove the resolution true or false. Since many resolutions have the word "ought," debaters can prove the truth or falsity of the resolution by proving there exists a moral obligation or prohibition upon doing the resolution. That is, if we have a moral obligation to do the resolution, then it is proven true that we ought to do the resolution, or vice-versa. | |||
Truth testing is also commonly paired with [[tricks]]. Some tricks, like [[A Prioris|a prioris]], function by proving that the resolution is inherently a true or false statement due to some logical or semantical property of the wording of the resolution. Other tricks, like [[Moral Skepticism|moral skepticism]], prove it is impossible to generate moral obligations, so the "ought" statement could never be proven true. | |||
Finally, truth testing can also be useful against [[Theory|theoretical]] or [[Kritiks|critical arguments]], as truth testing would exclude all offense that doesn't directly prove the resolution true or false. | |||
== Common Justifications == | |||
Here are some common justifications for truth testing. | |||
''Jurisdictional'' justifications for truth testing describe the way in which the judge determines the winner of the round. The judge only has the power to vote for the better debater because the ballot is specifically asking if the resolution is true or false in the given round which means the ballot is inherently asking for the truth or falsity of the resolution. | ''Jurisdictional'' justifications for truth testing describe the way in which the judge determines the winner of the round. The judge only has the power to vote for the better debater because the ballot is specifically asking if the resolution is true or false in the given round which means the ballot is inherently asking for the truth or falsity of the resolution. | ||
Line 12: | Line 19: | ||
''Resolvability'' justifications portray truth and falsity as a binary system of evaluating arguments in the round which makes it the most resolvable. Other role of the ballots would fail in truth testing's stead because it leaves it up to the judge (and perhaps their personal biases) to resolve the round. | ''Resolvability'' justifications portray truth and falsity as a binary system of evaluating arguments in the round which makes it the most resolvable. Other role of the ballots would fail in truth testing's stead because it leaves it up to the judge (and perhaps their personal biases) to resolve the round. | ||
== Responses == | |||
First, it is worth noting that you might not need to respond to truth testing. If you are reading a different philosophical framework that proves the resolution true or false, including [[utilitarianism]], you could concede truth testing and argue that your framework proves the resolution true or false, too. However, if you opponent is leveraging truth testing to gain access to many tricks, it still might be worth contesting truth testing and going for an alternative role of the ballot, such as [[comparative worlds]]. | |||
The most effective way to respond to truth testing, like any other role of the ballot, is to line-by-line the justifications and leverage your own role of the ballot. | |||
The most effective way | |||
=== Responses to Common Arguments === | |||
On ''Jurisdiction:'' Tab doesn't actually ask for the truth or falsity, but asks the judge whether they vote aff or neg which means it's not actually about the truth of the resolution. | On ''Jurisdiction:'' Tab doesn't actually ask for the truth or falsity, but asks the judge whether they vote aff or neg which means it's not actually about the truth of the resolution. | ||
On ''Inclusivity:'' Truth testing is not the most inclusive because it excludes arguments that don't prove the truth or falsity of the resolution. | On ''Inclusivity:'' Truth testing is not the most inclusive because it excludes arguments that don't prove the truth or falsity of the resolution. | ||
Line 32: | Line 33: | ||
On ''Resolvability:'' There may still be different conceptions of what is true and false. It may also be harder to resolve the round because you can't way between a claim of truth and a claim of falsity because they just clash. | On ''Resolvability:'' There may still be different conceptions of what is true and false. It may also be harder to resolve the round because you can't way between a claim of truth and a claim of falsity because they just clash. | ||